Untold

Essays

Prompt A - Staff Star Award

Lisette Partipilo

Lessons come in many forms inside and outside of a classroom. Reflect on a high school, college, or work assignment or achievement (such as a paper, performance, project, design, coding project, championship, medal, or other tangible accomplishment).

I received the “Staff Star Award” from the staff association at Salt Lake Community College in the spring of 2023. The truth is, this achievement made me feel more than just a “Star”, because I had an opportunity to feel “human.” That is, I was able to empathize with another during a stressful situation. This situation allowed me to acknowledge language as a first aid skill and use the power of communication as means to save a life.

It was a Monday morning, around 9:00 am. I was on my way to the Center for Health & Counseling, when I noticed a life-threatening situation on campus: a glass panel fell and shattered into a construction worker’s neck. People were frantic and asking for help. “How can I help?” I said, and they replied, “No English”. As a pre-medical student, I had a pair of gloves in my backpack, and while I was communicating with the patient in Spanish, my first language, I was also controlling the bleeding, and performing a physical examination, evaluating his airway, breathing, circulation, neurological deficit, and exposure. The ABCDE of trauma. My hands and a 4x4 gauze were a barrier between life and death, but the language difference was not, as I was able to indicate people how to call 911 and ask for help. The Taylorsville Fire Department responded within 5 minutes and controlled the scene. Interpreting from one language to another, I was able to provide a description of the accident, initial assessment of the wound, and medical history of interest from the patient.

Lessons come unexpectedly, and this experience was one of them. As of today, it is a daily reminder to value language as a resource to save a life beyond the clinical expertise taught in a classroom, and the importance of communicating with our patients, especially when their life is in our hands.

Disinformation: A Modern Problem

Andrew Kenney

Spring 2023

In academia, almost all of the scholars are trying to make sense of the “fake news” phenomena that has ravaged the internet. They are trying to define something that took off so quickly that they are still not sure exactly what it is. Even to this day, six years after the first real incidents of “fake news” started cropping up in the United States (the 2016 US election), experts are still scrambling to give it a proper definition and function. Yet simply defining “fake news” does not capture the scope of a government-backed disinformation campaign actively seeking to bend a population to their will. The United Nations needs to stop ignoring this problem and make disinformation punishable by more than just a simple fine.

READ MORE

Disinformation: A Modern Problem

Andrew Kenney

Introduction

In academia, almost all of the scholars are trying to make sense of the “fake news” phenomena that has ravaged the internet. They are trying to define something that took off so quickly that they are still not sure exactly what it is. Even to this day, six years after the first real incidents of “fake news” started cropping up in the United States (the 2016 US election), experts are still scrambling to give it a proper definition and function. Yet simply defining “fake news” does not capture the scope of a government-backed disinformation campaign actively seeking to bend a population to their will. The United Nations needs to stop ignoring this problem and make disinformation punishable by more than just a simple fine.

Throughout this article, I will explore what is currently being focused on by scholars. After identifying what these scholars missed, I will give a definitive definition of the various terms that appear in the works of these scholars. Following the exploration and proper definitions of false information, I will show why we should be focusing on combating disinformation (rather than defining it) by providing various examples of modern disinformation. Finally, I will explore a possible solution to the problem. My hope is that I can convey a sense of urgency about the underlying problem with merely defining and simply talking about disinformation.

Defining False Information

Even though I just criticized most scholars for focusing on defining disinformation, it’s still worth talking about because this is where the conversation begins. To start, many scholars question why false information doesn’t lose its momentum not long after it begins. Toma and Scripcariu tackle this by suggesting that there are five different definitions that misinformation can fall into: “recurrent occurrences,’ ‘scapegoat offensives,’ ‘pseudoscientific gaze,’ ‘combo strikes,’ and ‘humorous hijacks.”1

I would like to add a sixth definition called “absurd scams,” which is an idea that is so out of left field that it unironically is more believable. I will refer back to this in a moment. Toma and Scripcariu define the five examples as misinformation, but I think a few of these could definitely be defined as disinformation as well; scapegoat offensives, pseudoscientific gaze, and humorous hijacks could all be taken to the extremes and end up as disinformation. Baptista and Gradim build on what Toma and Scripcariu said, saying that many scholars reject these definitions, that they are “unstable’…[and] ‘absurd’ [in] meaning.”2 They then propose their own definition of disinformation, stating that it is “…intentionally designed to mislead and/or manipulate a specific or imagined public.”3 In most of the definitions that these scholars provide, it is implied that a foreign party—whether a person, state, or company—from a position of power—usually a political rival—disseminates false information to deteriorate an opposing viewpoint, often with physical consequences. I think it’s safe to say that every scholar agrees that disinformation is bad; however, my concern is still “What should we do about it?”

I mentioned “absurd scams” as an addendum to Toma and Scripcariu’s five misinformation ecosystems a little earlier. The concept of “absurd scams” is based on Miller’s article, in which he briefly describes a few attempts by the Russians to frame the Ukrainian Government in a bad light: the supposed crucifixion of a child by the Ukrainian Government, ISIS training camps set up and approved by the Ukrainian government, and the printing of Hitler’s face on their currency.4 To be perfectly clear, the aforementioned examples are fake; they have been debunked by StopFake.org—a non-profit organization dedicated to exposing disinformation spread by Kremlin media outlets.5 These are examples of absurd scams because they are way out of left field, and yet, there are those who believed them—hook, line, and sinker. Bockett proves why disinformation is so effective through soft balancing, yet he seems to have shouted into a void; not one of the recent articles I’ve read has mentioned his paper.6 Perhaps this is because soft balancing is a term associated with traditional warfare and hasn’t quite made its way to online interactions yet. Regardless, disinformation is a problem that hasn’t been addressed properly, and most scholars have yet to suggest any effective countermeasures against it.

Disinformation, Misinformation, and Fake News: An Examination of Discrepancies in Definitions

In order to understand why we shouldn’t be focusing on defining false information anymore, I decided to analyze how these terms showed up in previous academic articles. There are three different terms that appear in various contexts: “fake news,” disinformation, and misinformation. These three terms, although having separate meanings, are used in a way that makes it confusing for the reader to understand. In hindsight, I can see that these terms are indeed different—and for the most part, used properly; however, before I had come up with my definition, that was not obvious to me. For example, in Aswad’s article, “misinformation” is never seen without “disinformation,” and the only exception to that is in the footnotes, but it’s easy to overlook because the footnotes take up the entire page.7 A second example is that of Toma and Scripcariu’s Misinformation Ecosystems: A Typology of Fake News, in which they use misinformation as a synonym for “fake news,” as well as occasionally throwing disinformation into the mix.8 Again, prior to coming up with my definition, this confused me quite a bit. These are only a few examples of confusing terminology. There are many more examples, but that would warrant an entirely different paper.

Having examined various discrepancies of disinformation, misinformation, and “fake news,” I will set forth my definitions of the various terms in a way that is not confusing, vague, or misleading. Beginning with “fake news” of the modern era, this can be defined as a popular term coined by the media; it represents false information on an online platform. To further cement this definition, Baptista and Gradim’s article A Working Definition of Fake News agrees with my definition, where they describe “fake news” as “a type of online disinformation.”9 They do define “fake news” as disinformation—which is fine; however, I would still argue that “fake news” is coined by popular media as a means to scare people. If any more explanation is needed, then suffice it to say that the definition that I provided will be enough for this article.

Following “fake news” is misinformation, which can be defined as false information that was unintentionally produced. In other words, somebody got their facts wrong. While this isn’t nearly as destructive as disinformation, misinformation can have a harmful impact. A prime example of misinformation is a story I heard from one of my high school English teachers on November 21, 2022. In this story, my teacher had a neighbor who happened to be on the sex offenders list. Once the rest of the neighborhood found out, they were determined to root out this dangerous person from their peaceful, sex offender-less community. At first, my teacher was a part of that group. After doing some digging, however, he found out that this person on the sex offenders list was only there because he had sex with his wife before they were married. After learning this, my teacher did his best to spread the truth—the truth that this person was not a criminal to be afraid of. His efforts were in vain, as the family moved away not long after. This story goes to show that getting facts wrong can have serious consequences. It can ruin reputations, upset relationships, or, as we saw in this story, displace people. Misinformation, however, is only the lesser of the two evils.

Finally, we have disinformation, which can be defined as false information that is intentionally and deliberately disseminated to alter the opinion/viewpoint of a certain demographic. There are many examples of this—the most recent of which is right on our home turf in Orem. According to the Daily Herald, an email was sent from the South West Orem Neighborhood Association announcing that “Alpine School District Announces Orem School Closures!”10 There was also an article published on KSL (and later removed) labeling eight schools for closure and demolition in Orem.11 Needless to say, these false articles are local examples of disinformation, and undoubtedly affected the results of 2022’s mid-term elections in Orem, Utah. These definitions go to show that although these terms can be used collaboratively, one should be careful how they employ them—lest they confuse their audience.

Russia and Disinformation

One does not simply bring up disinformation without mentioning Russia. In every article about “fake news,” disinformation, or misinformation that I’ve read, Russia is brought up at least once. In Toma and Scripcariu’s article, they bring up a Russian social media game from 2017—known simply as the “Blue Whale”—in which the game appeared to be threatening a huge population, but the reality was that the impact was small and rather insignificant.12 Although the article mentions that this occurred in Romania, this instance should not be casually thrown aside; it shows how much Russian influence affects everyone.13 Moving to more modern times and the current issue of Russia and Ukraine, Miller describes how Russia lies to the Russophones in Ukraine, creating fictitious stories to persuade them to abandon the “fascist” government and return to Russia.14 These efforts have been so effective, that the Donbass and Crimea regions of Ukraine “…came to support… separation from Ukraine or outright annexation by Russia.”15 Bockett confirms what Miller says, saying that this strategy—which he coins as “soft balancing”—has been “…much more effective…than traditional military…strategies.”16 This strategy is so effective, it caused Dawson and Innes to write an entire article on how the Russians handled their disinformation campaign, exploring the various methods of how the Internet Research Agency (IRA) influenced the various countries of the world.17 They gain notoriety on Twitter (and therefore, influence) through a combination of these three methods: buying followers, follower fishing, and narrative switching.18 All of this goes to show that the Russians have perfected the art of manipulation through false information—and not just propaganda in their home country.

Disinformation as Warfare

At the turn of the millennium, as the internet exploded in popularity, and the world became more interconnected, the ability to spy on, steal from, and attack other countries was becoming easier than ever. As Eun and Aßmann state, “cyber operations alone…have the potential to [become] international armed conflict.”19 They also argue that information, specifically online information, will become a fifth platform off of which to wage war.20 Although the focus of their article is on digital weapons that have kinetic consequences, their argument can also be applied to disinformation as well. Bockett elaborates on this through his concept of soft balancing—decreasing a rival’s power versus increasing one’s own power.21 Miller shows soft balancing in the Russo-Ukrainian War of 2022, in which Russia floods Ukrainian media with blatantly false information, and Ukraine fights back with memes—a sort of front-line defense for those on social media, piloted by the North Atlantic Fellas Organization, or NAFO.22 The examples above are only a few examples of how disinformation has been weaponized, and the list is only growing.

A Modern Conflict

Now that the dangers of disinformation have been revealed, I can continue on by showing how disinformation is affecting the world today. The first instances of disinformation that I can find were a result of the Euromaidan Revolution in 2014—a revolution in Ukraine caused by the refusal to join the EU. Prior to the Euromaidan, a Russian sympathizer occupied the president's chair, and the Russians spread their thoughts and ideas through various news channels—primarily social media.23 During and after the Euromaidan, Russian media outlets labeled the revolutionists as “fascists’ and ‘brutal Russophobic thugs.”24 The worst part? Those in the Donbass and Crimea regions believed this—hook, line, and sinker.25 In case it wasn’t obvious, these accusations are false; they were spread by the Russians in an attempt to bring Ukraine back under Russian control. Fast forward to 2016, the Russians have taken an interest in US politics.26 According to Time magazine, the Russians hacked into the Clinton campaign network, stole emails and passwords, and used it to produce negative news against Clinton, and that was only a small slice of what they did.27 According to Bauer and Hohenberg, the Denver Guardian—a false media outlet based on the Guardian—spread false information about Hillary Clinton that attracted hundreds of thousands of views, and undoubtedly altered the results of the election.28 In 2017, Russia decided to pull the strings in a second country—France. Had they succeeded, Marin Le Pen—the candidate that the Russians backed—would have removed France from the EU, likely creating political unrest throughout Europe.29 All of this goes to show that Russia is actively affecting global politics through disinformation, and, as far as I am aware, nobody has done anything about it.

These disinformation campaigns are not isolated to the past. They continue on today, right under the nose of the worst war seen in decades—the Russo-Ukrainian War. In the weeks leading up to the invasion of Ukraine, the Russians began saying the Ukrainian military was about to attack the Donetsk and Luhansk regions—both of which are inside Ukraine’s borders.30 A few days before the invasion, they created a video of the supposed shelling of a civilian town, in which the “citizen” lost a leg.31 As the war started, videos of the alleged “Ghost of Kyiv” were created by the Russians to spread false hope among Ukrainian supporters.32 Once again, disinformation is not a thing of the past. Disinformation is a vital tool in the Russian arsenal, and they are using it very liberally.

That’s not to say that Ukrainians aren’t fighting back. Ever since the Euromaidan, StopFake has been debunking Russian disinformation non-stop.33 In fact, they are still debunking disinformation to this day. They are not the only ones combatting the disinformation onslaught, however. An online community known as the North Atlantic Fellas Organization, or NAFO, has banded together to debunk the Russian disinformation on the front lines, so to speak. NAFO is known for creating memes that involve the popular Shiba Inu dog. This has gotten so large that Adam Taylor, a reporter for The Washington Post, wrote an entire article on NAFO.34 Spreading memes about Russian disinformation, however, won’t stop it from happening.

An Idea to Proactively Counter Disinformation

Although Russian disinformation is being constantly debunked, simply debunking disinformation isn’t enough. Something needs to be done that will prevent disinformation from affecting a population again. Unfortunately, there is no framework to go off of—simply because this form of disinformation is much newer and harder to identify. The closest thing I can find to a possible framework is the United Nation’s Atrocity Crimes—more specifically, the page on Crimes Against Humanity. Using these guidelines, I would argue that disinformation—especially when it is backed by the government—would fall under the persecution category, fulfilling the physical element of the crime.

Am I bending the definition of “persecution” to fit my needs? I don’t think so. Seeing as persecution is defined as hostility due to race, political or religious beliefs, I think Russian disinformation fits this definition rather well, if not perfectly. The physical element isn’t the only thing that needs to be considered, however. According to the UN, there needs to be a contextual and mental element considered in tandem with the physical element. The contextual element is defined as “…[a] part of a widespread or systematic attack directed against any civilian population.”35 The Russian disinformation campaign is indeed a part of a greater whole; in case you weren’t aware, that greater whole is the war that’s been going on for almost a year now. Finally, the mental element requires that the attacker must have knowledge of the attack. I would argue that Putin is very aware of this, especially because he has a branch of his government dedicated to doing just that—the Internet Research Agency, or IRA.36 Therefore, with all three categories’ requirements met, I would argue that Vladimir Putin is indeed a war criminal and should be dealt with accordingly.

There are those that would see my solution as censorship—after all, I am arguing that disinformation should be, well, censored. These people have good reasons, too. After all, censorship laws are generally created to identify and eliminate those that are against a certain political regime. A prime example of this is an instance that occurred in Singapore in 2019. Although it was well-intentioned, a law banning “fake news” was used “…for the purpose of silencing a regime critic, rather than for the reasons originally cited…”37 As a counterpoint to the censorship law abuse, I would argue that censorship laws must be handled by an international court, a separate entity that (ideally) would have no biases and could examine the potential offenders with a clean slate. Finally, to quote Aswad once more, this does indeed involve “…an enumerated public interest objective…” seeing as there are lives on the line.38

Conclusion

Information—which was once thought to be useful only when it was tangible—has now been weaponized on a level never seen before. Information has become the fifth platform off of which to wage war (if it wasn’t already). Disinformation—which is deliberately disseminated false information—has been used to sway the opinions of those who would otherwise be an enemy, as seen with Russia and Ukraine. While StopFake and NAFO are helping fight this disinformation, they can’t do everything on their own. This is why I have argued so heavily for laws against international disinformation. Something needs to be done, and not just a slap on the wrist. The time to stop defining disinformation is long past us—that was way back in February of 2022. We need to start combating disinformation and curb this problem as soon as possible—not just for the benefit of Ukraine, but for the entire world.

  1. Gabriel-Alexandru Toma and Adina-Gabriela Scripcariu, “Misinformation Ecosystems: A Typology of Fake News,” Journal of Comparative Research in Anthropology & Sociology 11, no. 2 (December 1, 2020): 65, https://doaj.org/article/41fe44ccef5241f08f0a0791200fcaad.
  2. João Pedro Baptista and Anabela Gradim, “A Working Definition of Fake News,” Encyclopedia 2, no. 1 (March 1, 2022): 632, https://doi:10.3390/encyclopedia2010043.
  3. Baptista and Gradim, “A Working Definition,” 632.
  4. Nash Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare in Ukraine,” Russian Analytical Digest, no. 282 (April 12, 2022): 5, https://doi:10.3929/ethz-b-000541999.
  5. Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare,” 4.
  6. Daryl Bockett, “Virtual Theory: Integrating Cybersecurity into International Relations Theory,” International Journal of Interdisciplinary Global Studies 12, no. 4 (October 1, 2017): 20-21, https://doi:10.18848/2324-755X/CGP/v12i04/15-30.
  7. Evelyn Mary Aswad, “In a World of ‘Fake News,’ What’s a Social Media Platform to Do?” Utah Law Review 2020, no. 4 (January 1, 2020): 1001, https://doi.org/10.26054/0D-TGXD-4V9T.
  8. Toma and Scripcariu, “Misinformation Ecosystems,” 65.
  9. Baptista and Gradim, “A Working Definition,” 640.
  10. Ashtyn Asay, “Alpine School District Responds to Allegations of School Closures,” Daily Herald, October 20, 2022, https://www.heraldextra.com/news/local/2022/oct/20/asd-responds-to-allegations-of-school-closures/.
  11. KSL NewsRadio Staff, “Letter from the newsroom: We pulled an inaccurate article,” KSL NewsRadio, October 20, 2022, https://kslnewsradio.com/1977505/letter-from-the-newsroom-we-pulled-an-inaccurate-article/.
  12. Toma and Scripcariu, “Misinformation Ecosystems,” 75-76.
  13. Toma and Scripcariu, “Misinformation Ecosystems,” 75.
  14. Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare,” 3.
  15. Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare,” 3.
  16. Bockett, “Virtual Theory,” 20-21.
  17. Andrew Dawson and Martin Innes, “How Russia’s Internet Research Agency Built Its Disinformation Campaign,” Political Quarterly 90, no. 2 (June 1, 2019): 245–256, https://doi:10.1111/1467-923X.12690.
  18. Dawson and Innes, “How Russia’s Internet Research Agency,” 247-249.
  19. Yong-Soo Eun and Judith Sita Aßmann, “Cyberwar: Taking Stock of Security and Warfare in the Digital Age,” International Studies Perspectives 17, no. 3 (January 1, 2016): 344, https://doi: 10.1111/insp.12073.
  20. Eun and Aßmann, “Cyberwar,” 357.
  21. Bocket, “Virtual Theory,” 20-21.
  22. Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare,” 3-4.
  23. Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare,” 3.
  24. Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare,” 3.
  25. Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare,” 3.
  26. Bockett, “Virtual Theory,” 18-19.
  27. Abigail Abrams, “Here’s What We Know So Far About Russia’s 2016 Meddling,” Time, April 18, 2019, https://time.com/5565991/russia-influence-2016-election/.
  28. Paul C. Bauer and Bernhard Clemm von Hohenberg, “Believing and Sharing Information by Fake Sources: An Experiment,” Political Communication 38, no. 6 (December 1, 2021): 649, https://doi:10.1080/10584609.2020.1840462.
  29. Bockett, “Virtual Theory,” 19.
  30. Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare,” 3.
  31. Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare,” 3.
  32. Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare,” 5.
  33. Miller, “Adaptive Russian Information Warfare,” 4.
  34. Adam Taylor, “With NAFO, Ukraine Turns the Trolls on Russia,” The Washington Post, September 1, 2022, https://www.washingtonpost.com/world/2022/09/01/nafo-ukraine-russia/.
  35. “Crimes Against Humanity,” United Nations Office on Genocide Prevention and the Responsibility to Protect, https://www.un.org/en/genocideprevention/crimes-against-humanity.shtml.
  36. Dawson and Innes, “How Russia’s Internet Research Agency,” 245.
  37. Aswad, “In a World,” 1019-1020.
  38. Aswad, “In a World,” 1014.

The Elephant in the Room: The Reality of Pluralism in John Hick’s Pluralistic Hypothesis

Lizzy Jensen

An old Eastern parable tells a story of six blind men and an elephant. Ignorant of the nature and stature of this animal, the blind men are led to the elephant to touch, describe, and make a claim of what this unknown object might be. One man feels the trunk and insists it must be a snake. Another touches the tail and claims it must be a rope. Another grasps the papery ear and decides it must be a fan. The purpose of this parable is to showcase that each human being may see and observe a phenomenon and claim absolute truth based on their perception of the phenomenon. In the modern day of increasing globalization and diversity, this parable is often used as an analogy to illustrate the spectrum of religious beliefs.

Read More

The Elephant in the Room: The Reality of Pluralism in John Hick’s Pluralistic Hypothesis

Lizzy Jensen

 

Introduction

An old Eastern parable tells a story of six blind men and an elephant. Ignorant of the nature and stature of this animal, the blind men are led to the elephant to touch, describe, and make a claim of what this unknown object might be. One man feels the trunk and insists it must be a snake. Another touches the tail and claims it must be a rope. Another grasps the papery ear and decides it must be a fan. The purpose of this parable is to showcase that each human being may see and observe a phenomenon and claim absolute truth based on their perception of the phenomenon. In the modern day of increasing globalization and diversity, this parable is often used as an analogy to illustrate the spectrum of religious beliefs.

Other analogies are used to such an end: fingers pointing to the same moon, cars driving several different highways to the same city, and various pathways taken up the same mountain. Each analogy, though fluctuating slightly, attempts to shine a light of similarity in the murky and oft troubled sea of religious difference. In 1989, religious philosopher John Hick published his pluralistic hypothesis in An Interpretation of Religion as a way to calm these waters of divergence. Hick proposed that all humankind is religiously experiencing the same Reality, but in their own distinct and culturally conditioned way. He claims that “the great world faiths embody different perceptions and conceptions of, and correspondingly different responses to, the Real from within the major variant ways of being human.”1 Despite the many differences between faith practices and beliefs, Hick holds that they all come from the same divine Reality.

Hick’s pluralistic hypothesis and the other parables and analogies referenced are well intentioned yet misguided. In attempting to establish similarities among humanity’s great religions, the particularities of religious belief are reduced to abstraction; these analogies neglect that the moon is still the moon, an elephant is still an elephant, and each must be logically defined in all its possibilities and limitations. I will provide examples of this abstraction in Hick’s philosophy of pluralism and further explain the reality of religious diversity and other sound philosophies that embrace what D.Z. Phillips defines as “radical pluralism.” Despite the shortcomings of Hick’s pluralistic attempt, difference in experience and belief should not hinder relationships across faiths.

Religious Pluralism and Relativism

To a hopeful defendant of interfaith relationships among religious diversity, Hick’s hypothesis is affirming at first glance. He argues for the rational justification that “treating one’s own form of religious experience as a cognitive response . . . to a divine reality must . . . apply equally to the religious experience of others.”2 However, his ensuing argument begins to falter as he claims that the great world religions “constitute different ways of experiencing, conceiving, and living in relation to an ultimate divine Reality which transcends all our varied versions of it.”3 He goes on to define this divine Reality by way of not defining it, other than its characteristic of ineffability that seems to be shared across many belief systems. He claims that the Real “cannot be said to be one or many, person or thing, substance or process, good or evil, purposive or non-purposive . . . we cannot even speak of this as a thing or an entity.”4 Indeed, Gregory of Nyssa explains the Christian God “to be that which He is, [namely], incapable of being grasped by any term, or any idea, or any other device of our apprehension,”5 the Tao Te Ching affirms that “the Tao that can be told is not the eternal Tao,”6 and the Surah As-Saffat in the Qur’an praises, “Exalted is Allah above what they describe.”7 Clearly ineffability is a common conviction of the status of a religious Reality.

Hick does not acknowledge that these descriptions of a religion’s divine Reality as ineffable come with previous knowledge of such Reality’s identity. Keith Ward identifies this defect in Hick’s hypothesis as the difference between ontology and epistemology in matters of religious belief. He writes, “ineffability cannot in any case be sensibly interpreted to mean, ‘Lack of knowledge’ . . . That is, it is not that I do not know what God is; I do know that the being of God is such that it contains no distinctions, no parts, no complexity which human concepts could grasp.”8 In short, the ineffability of God or the eternal Tao is not epistemological, as there is clearly no failure for one to know and believe in their respective divine Reality; it is ontological, for ineffability is yet another way for divine Reality to be described, and in some cases, praised.

Hick’s claim to ineffability as the uniting factor of differing belief systems accelerates his hypothesis toward relativism. It removes the significance of distinct religious beliefs and abstracts the identity of each religion’s divine Reality. Roger Trigg identifies this problem and writes,

A realist understanding of religion, insisting that religion is about objective reality, portrays the very essence of religion . . . God must make himself accessible to man, if man is able to grasp his reality . . . [Hick’s] attempts to produce agreement between Christians and, say, Buddhists, can only proceed by emptying the claims of either, or both, of all real content.9

Appealing to relativism in matters so important to personal identity as religious belief is not a sustainable or logical answer to religious pluralism. Without an attainable definition of the nature of God or Dharma or Allah, a believer is left to wonder what there even is for them to believe in. Hick further claims in his pluralistic hypothesis that each of the world’s great faiths have “within each of them the transformation of human existence from self-centeredness to Reality-centeredness.”10 Such a transformation is not theologically possible if one does not feel that they know whatever Reality it is that they are aspiring to or worshiping.

Drawing similarities between religious and worldview beliefs can be an excellent way to encourage acceptance of difference in thought, and I believe that this was Hick’s intention. I do not doubt that his aspiration for his pluralistic hypothesis was to “provide a framework for interfaith dialogue” and encourage the traditions to respect and learn from each other.10 But Hick’s claims in his pluralistic hypothesis wax far too relativistic to encourage an interfaith dialogue in lasting and meaningful ways. Trigg addresses this problem by pointing out that “relativism, in fact, must breed indifference to other religions, while any claim of objective truth must be taken seriously by anyone.”11 Such indifference may prevent meaningful relationships between faiths as it eludes conversation about differing ideologies and allows the relativist to avoid thinking critically and deeply about their beliefs and the beliefs of others. If one is too frightened to express a claim to truth, their beliefs are not able to be fully seen and understood by others.

Religious Pluralism and Contemplative Philosophy

D.Z. Phillips further addresses these flaws in Hick’s hypothesis and introduces contemplative philosophy as a more logical approach to understanding religious pluralism. He identifies contemplative philosophy as an “attempt to do conceptual justice to the world in all its variety.”12 Phillips’ thesis is that pluralism, in the way Hick writes his hypothesis, is elbowed away from being a philosophical concept and becomes a theological concept. It is held up as a third option against the theological perspectives of exclusivism and inclusivism. When improperly compared with these two perspectives, the word “pluralism” is wrongfully understood as the thought process that 1) all the world religions are different paths to the same God, or 2) closer to Hick’s hypothesis that “God” transcends all religions and is only half-understood by each one. Both of those perspectives falter logically, as has already been pointed out. Phillips argues that those two perspectives on pluralism have “no interest in doing conceptual justice to religions, no matter what their character.”13 Instead of looking deeply at different belief systems and their practices, this path of theological pluralism gives permission for outside parties to opt for the backseat instead of curiously engaging with faiths and worldviews that are different from their own.

Phillips instead claims that radical pluralism is successful philosophical contemplation of different religions. This approach to religious pluralism does not deny the existence of difference and conflict among religions, but allows those differences to exist, as they are. Radical pluralism can be especially understood in the context of the human sacrifice performed by the Aztecs. Instead of writing off human sacrifices as a terrible, mistaken understanding of the Real, radical pluralism contemplates the actuality of the ritual of human sacrifice and “does conceptual justice to such rituals by recognizing them as a part of the radical pluralism of human life.”14 Radical pluralism does not theologically explain away the persistence of these rituals but explores them as a human phenomenon.

Radical pluralism may seem impossible to obtain. It is unrealistic for the thoughtful philosopher to live constantly in such contemplation because, as Phillips pointed out, they have “a life to live.”15 Indeed, as a pluralist myself, I acknowledge that I am partial to Christianity, and I have built a home of beliefs and values wherein I have chosen to live. Naturally, those values and beliefs will come in conflict with others. But radical pluralism does not demand the complete removal of conflict. In fact, the true pluralist must accept that such religious conflict is inevitable. I turn again to Keith Ward:

Both atheists and theists [and nontheists] can be rationally justified in adopting the views of the world they do adopt . . . but it does not follow that each must accept the other’s view as equally true . . . So I must admit the equal right of others to exist and hold the views they do. And I must admit the fallibility and theoretical uncertainty of my view.16

Radical pluralism is acknowledging that human life consists of many different possibilities of meaning. The contemplative pluralist is not forced to accept all possibilities, but is encouraged to merely recognize and respect them.

A commitment to religious pluralism does not require a relinquishment or abstraction of one’s personal religious beliefs. In practical application, Hick’s hypothesis appeals for a believer to water down their own religious belief to theologically make room for others. Generalizing religious belief in such a way is dangerous to the distinction and transcendence of religious belief across the world. D.Z. Phillips claims that contemplative philosophy “is not a retreat from life, a lack of interest in the fray, but a certain kind of interest in human life, born of wonder at it.”17 It is my desire that such wonder at religious life and belief will obtain the interfaith dialogue of which John Hick was so hopeful when he first established his pluralistic hypothesis.

  1. John Hick, An Interpretation of Religion: Human Responses to the Transcendent (London: Yale University Press, 1989), 240.
  2. Hick, An Interpretation of Religion, 235.
  3. Hick, An Interpretation of Religion, 235-236.
  4. Hick, An Interpretation of Religion, 246
  5. Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, trans. William Moore and Henry Austin Wilson (New York: Christian Literature Publishing), 1.42, https://www.newadvent.org/fathers/290101.htm.
  6. Lao-tzu, Tao Te Ching, trans. Stephen Mitchell (EPub: Harper Collins, 2004), 15, https://docdrop.org/download_annotation_doc/-Perennial-Classics-Lao-Tzu-Stephen-Mitchell---Tao-Te-Ching_-A-New-English-Version-Harper-Perennial-Modern-Classics-2006-2-4--pDMw9.pdf.
  7. The Qur’an 37:159, trans. Saheeh International, https://alrashidmosque.ca/wp-content/uploads/2019/05/The-Quran-Saheeh-International.pdf.
  8. Keith Ward, “Truth and the Diversity of Religions,” Religious Studies 26, no. 1 (March 1990): 6, https://www.jstor.org/stable/20019384.
  9. Roger Trigg, “Religion and the Threat of Relativism,” Religious Studies 19, no. 3 (September 1983): 304, 298, https://www.jstor.org/stable/20005971.
  10. John Hick, An Interpretation of Religion... (London: Yale University Press), 240.
  11. Trigg, “Religion and the Threat of Relativism,” 300.
  12. D.Z. Phillips, “Philosophy’s Radical Pluralism in the House of Intellect,” in D.Z. Phillips' Contemplative Philosophy of Religion: Questions and Responses, ed. Andy Sanders (New York: Ashgate Publishing, 2007), 207, https://research.ebsco.com/linkprocessor/plink?id=f60f5816-a3c8-3b9c-8def-09ebff804fbe.
  13. Phillips, “...Questions and Responses,” 204-205.
  14. Phillips, “...Questions and Responses,” 205.
  15. Phillips, “...Questions and Responses,” 207.
  16. Ward, “Truth and the Diversity of Religions,” 13.
  17. Phillips, “...Questions and Responses,” 207.

Image of a rock wall that people are preparing to climb

Rapid Rascals

Megan Charchenko

Rapid Rascals is a blog written by upper division communication students with the intent to teach people how to function in a healthy small group. Each article gives a different perspective and lesson on how to have safe and healthy small-group communication.

SEE MORE